Jonathan Haidt begins his book, The Righteous Mind, with the late Rodney King’s famous quote, “Why
can’t we all get along?” Haidt then goes on to explain quite the opposite
phenomenon; the uniquely human capacity for people to form large non-kin groups
and work together in more or less harmony to achieve common goals.
According to Haidt the key that
unlock this capacity for cooperation are humankind’s evolved ability to create
moral systems which he defines as “interlocking sets of values,
virtues, norms, practices, identities, institutions, and technologies that mesh
well with evolved psychological mechanisms and thereby enable the community to
suppress or regulate selfishness and make cooperation possible.” Humans have evolved a set of intuitive moral
reflexes or appetites that help us to jointly protect our mutual and individual
interests so we can get along in groups and collectively protect ourselves from
other groups. There are three aspects to this theory.
First, moral
judgments arise from innate instinctive reflexes; they are not derived from
reason. In fact reason is almost always
used to create post hoc rationales for the moral decision we have already made.
Second, these innate
moral intuitions or appetites seem to fall into six categories, care/harm,
fairness/cheating, freedom/subjugation, community/anarchy,
authority/insubordination, and sanctity/degradation. Different groups tend to value these moral
appetites differently. Haidt points out that, universally, liberals put far
more weight on the appetites of care and fairness whereas conservatives give
more balanced weight to all six appetites.
Third, moral
appetites evolved not only to motivate individuals to protect self-interest,
but also to motivate individuals to respond to threats and protect group
interests. Haidt calls institutions that support these moral appetites moral
capital. They are particularly morally
compelling because they give us the opportunity to become part of something
bigger than ourselves. They almost exclusively fall into the category of
community (Support the troops), authority (Respect the president), and sanctity
(respect the flag).
Haidt acknowledges
that conflict can arise within groups (liberal vs. conservative Americans) or
between groups (secular humanist west vs. Islamist middle east), but, for the
most part, he attributes these conflicts to differences in emphasis on the
various moral appetites. He implies that
if we understood these differences more completely we could all get along a lot
better. He concludes the book with the following hopeful advise.
“We are deeply intuitive creatures whose gut
feelings drive our strategic reasoning.
This makes it difficult – but not impossible – to connect with those who
live in other (moral) matrices which are often built on different
configurations of the available moral foundations.
So the next time you find yourself seated
beside someone from another (moral) matrix, give it a try. Don’t just jump
right in. Don’t bring up morality until you’ve found a few points of
commonality or in some other way established a bit of trust. And when you do bring up issues of morality,
try to start with some praise, or with a sincere expression of interest.
We’re all stuck here for a while, so let’s
try to work it out.”
However, if one
looks a little more closely at conflicts both within and between groups these
conflicts are far more intransigent and morality is precisely the problem.
Alexis de Tocqueville pointed out in
Of honor in the United States and in
democratic communities from volume II of Democracy in America that conflicting values can arise within groups when a set of rules is
implemented as a means of suppressing one group to advance the interest of
another. He doesn’t call this a moral code but instead uses the term honor
which he defines as, “ . . . the aggregate of those rules by the aid of
which . . . esteem, glory, or reverence is obtained.”
In aristocratic, that is hierarchical societies a small
group of people at the top of the hierarchy had to maintain power over those
they ruled. They
created this particular form of morality so that their class could maintain
power over all others.
As
de Tocqueville puts it, “A class which
has succeeded in placing itself above all others, and which makes perpetual
exertions to maintain this lofty position, must especially honor those virtues
which are conspicuous for their dignity and splendor and which may be easily
combined with pride and the love of power. “
De
Tocqueville sees morality in more conventional liberal terms. The basic
function of this system is to bring people together and is based on care and
fairness. “It is the general and
permanent interest of mankind that men should not kill each other . . .” He
further notes that “It often happens that these two standards
differ; they sometimes conflict” as when;
“Some actions have been
held to be at the same time virtuous and dishonorable; a refusal to fight a
duel is an instance. “
“To debauch a woman of
color scarcely injures the reputation of an American; to marry her dishonors
him.”
Nonetheless, this
honor code “at the periods of its greatest power sways the will more than the belief
of men . . .” That is, it precisely fits
Haidt’s definition of moral thought; it is a . . . deeply intuitive . . . gut feeling that drives strategic thinking.”
If
what de Tocqueville calls honor then is a value system evoking the same
emotions and the same neural pathways as morality, then what it really is is
morality by another name but used for other purposes, namely as a means to
separate people for the purpose exerting power over them.
DeToqueville
believed that as society became more egalitarian this brand of morality would
gradually disappear and this for the most part is true.
However,
this same dynamic takes place when we consider conflicts between groups. Furthermore, it is probably far older,
stronger (hardwired), and more prevalent today than the moral conventions that
separate class. Where this value system has been rampant throughout history is
in religion. It is in fact codified in
western monotheistic religions where Jews, Christians, and Muslims have some
variation of, “Love thy neighbor as thy self.” (Binding Morality) and “Though
shalt have no other God but mine.” (Honor/Separating Morality)
As
a result, you love your neighbor as long as they do or don’t believe in the
pope, do or don’t believe God gave the land to you, or do or don’t ever print
pictures of the prophet. In all those cases you kill your neighbor.
While
religion has been the conventional system for creating lethal group
distinctions for most of human history, eliminating God doesn’t solve the
problem and the lack of a God may only exacerbate the problem. Nazi’s killed millions and communists killed
10’s of millions in the name of racial and ideological purity respectively.
Where
a value system is invoked to separate rather than bring people together the
moral stand is one that is based on either authority or purity and very
occasionally community. The point of invoking this value system is to exert
power over another person or group. I
can harm you, cheat you, take away your freedom, or exclude you from my group
because you are immoral on grounds of either authority (who you do or don’t revere) or purity (you don’t adhere
to rituals that defines my group).
However,
eliminating moral appetites based on authority and purity would be both
impossible (like eliminating taste and touch) and harmful. As Haidt points out
in the third part of his book it is in the cultivation moral capital that man
finds meaning in shared group practices.
It gives man the opportunity to become part of something bigger than
himself and can motivate him to some of mankind’s highest endeavors. Gandhi,
Mother Theresa, and Martin Luther King created meaning for themselves and the
world, motivated by their adherence to their values of authority and religious
ritual (purity).
On
the other hand the quest for meaning through adherence to exclusionary
authority and ritual can lead to the worst excesses of human depravity. We see
it today when thousands young men and women, sensing the culture they live in
bankrupt of moral capital, leave their comfortable lives in the west and travel
to the middle east to commit the most heinous moral atrocities in the name of
well - morality.
As
Haidt comprehensively makes the case, morality is the answer to why we can get
along at all.
Unfortunately,
it is also the answer to the question, “Why can’t we all get along?”
Geoffrey
Berg MD
References:
The Righteous Mind: Why Good
People Are Divided by Politics and Religion,
Jonathan Haidt First Vintage Books
01/2013
Democracy in America Volume II section 3 Chapter XVIII Of honor in the United States and in democratic communities Alexis de Tocqueville,
http://xroads.virginia.edu/~HYPER/DETOC/ch3_18.htm
Really nice post, Geoff. Haidt (and many others) have pointed out that pragmatic goals can unify people, providing a COMMON PURPOSE that underlies collaboration even when it is in conflict with moral sensibilities and moral, post-hoc reasoning. Using your example, we understand how a conditional love for your neighbor may be contingent on beliefs, "as long as they do or don’t believe in the pope, do or don’t believe God gave the land to you, or do or don’t ever print pictures of the prophet." But we have all also experienced how positive feelings for your neighbor can emerge from collaborative, shared experiences such as caring for a neighborhood school or park or store, even when you disagree with one another and unable to compromise on moral grounds. This is precisely the power of integration and the "commons" to know and humanize the "other" and, conversely, the potential of segregation to alienate and dehumanize.
ReplyDelete